On the Evolutionary Relativity of Intelligence and Consciousness

Published: March 2025
"We dissect nature along lines laid down by our native language." – Benjamin Lee Whorf

Our belief that human intelligence and consciousness are "special" arises because we are the ones experiencing them from the inside.

I'm not denying that human consciousness or our capacity for intelligent reasoning is impressive. Clearly, it represents a high degree of cognitive sophistication. But I think it's important to reframe how we view these traits. We often assume that our intelligence is inherently superior or that consciousness is something uniquely special. That assumption may be the result of a deep anthropocentric bias.

What if our intelligence isn't special in any absolute sense, but is simply the natural consequence of how our biological system adapted to its environment? Different systems—biological or otherwise—adapt to their environments in different ways. The specific structure and function of a system are shaped by the pressures it faces, and intelligence, as we define it, may just be one such adaptation.

In other words, the way we reason, solve problems, and experience self-awareness could be less about being "the pinnacle of evolution" and more about being an outcome of the kind of environment we evolved in. Intelligence, then, isn't a universal standard—it's one possible solution among many to the problem of surviving and thriving in a particular niche.

From this perspective, consciousness and intelligent reasoning are not inherently more "advanced" than other forms of adaptive behavior—they are just different. We might be biased toward viewing them as special because we possess them, but that doesn't make them objectively superior. A system with a completely different structure and environmental context might develop forms of adaptation that are equally complex but look nothing like what we call "intelligence."

Perhaps, even more profoundly, we get caught in a sort of cognitive trap that our unique human capacity for language helps construct. The only reason why we can articulate, debate, and ultimately perceive consciousness as "special" is because our linguistic framework itself frames consciousness as special. Our language provides us with specific words like "consciousness," "mind," "self," and "spirit." These aren't merely neutral labels; they are concepts laden with historical, philosophical, and cultural weight, each implicitly elevating the very idea they describe. By giving consciousness a name, we grant it an explicit point of reference – it becomes a distinct entity we can identify, isolate, and discuss, rather than an undifferentiated aspect of ongoing experience. This linguistic act of naming then feeds back into our perception. When we utter phrases like "I am conscious," this very assertion, framed by the specific words and grammar of our language, reinforces the notion of "consciousness" as a definable, bounded, and often exceptional quality. The specialness of consciousness is thus intrinsically tied to our linguistic description of consciousness, creating a powerful, self-reinforcing loop where the concept's perceived uniqueness is, in part, an artifact of its naming and the conceptual scaffolding our words provide.

So, rather than seeing intelligence and consciousness as endpoints of some linear evolutionary ladder, it makes more sense to see them as context-dependent phenomena—emergent properties of particular systems shaped by particular pressures. They are specific adaptations for specific challenges.

To put it simply: perhaps intelligence is not inherently special; it's environmentally and linguistically relative. And our belief in its specialness might just be a byproduct of self-reinforcing human narratives and the very words we use to define and articulate our experience.